From Casetext: Smarter Legal Research

City of Austin, Tex. v. Reagan Nat'l Advert. of Austin

Supreme Court of the United States
Apr 21, 2022
142 S. Ct. 1464 (2022)

Summary

cautioning against overreading Reed's "function or purpose" language

Summary of this case from People for the Ethical Treatment of Animals, Inc. v. N.C. Farm Bureau Fed'n

Opinion

No. 20-1029

04-21-2022

CITY OF AUSTIN, TEXAS, Petitioner v. REAGAN NATIONAL ADVERTISING OF AUSTIN, LLC, et al.

Michael R. Dreeben, Washington, DC, for the petitioner. Benjamin Snyder, for the United States as amicus curiae, by special leave of the Court, supporting the petitioner Kannon Shanmugam, Washington, DC, for the respondents. Anne L. Morgan, City Attorney, Meghan L. Riley, Chief-Litigation, H. Gray Laird III, Asst. City Att'y., City Of Austin Law Department, Austin, TX, Heather Welles, O'Melveny & Myers LLP, Los Angeles, CA, Renea Hicks, Counsel of Record, Law Office of Max Renea Hicks, Austin, TX, Michael R. Dreeben, Jeremy R. Girton, Rachel A. Chung, O'Melveny & Myers LLP, Washington, DC, for Petitioner. B. Russell Horton, George, Brothers, Kincaid & Horton, LLP, Austin, TX, Kannon K. Shanmugam, Counsel of Record, Aimee W. Brown, William T. Marks, Elizabeth A. Norford, Paul, Weiss, Rifkind, Wharton & Garrison LLP, Washington, DC, Sarah J. Prostko, Paul, Weiss, Rifkind, Wharton & Garrison LLP, New York, NY, for Respondents.


Michael R. Dreeben, Washington, DC, for the petitioner.

Benjamin Snyder, for the United States as amicus curiae, by special leave of the Court, supporting the petitioner

Kannon Shanmugam, Washington, DC, for the respondents.

Anne L. Morgan, City Attorney, Meghan L. Riley, Chief-Litigation, H. Gray Laird III, Asst. City Att'y., City Of Austin Law Department, Austin, TX, Heather Welles, O'Melveny & Myers LLP, Los Angeles, CA, Renea Hicks, Counsel of Record, Law Office of Max Renea Hicks, Austin, TX, Michael R. Dreeben, Jeremy R. Girton, Rachel A. Chung, O'Melveny & Myers LLP, Washington, DC, for Petitioner.

B. Russell Horton, George, Brothers, Kincaid & Horton, LLP, Austin, TX, Kannon K. Shanmugam, Counsel of Record, Aimee W. Brown, William T. Marks, Elizabeth A. Norford , Paul, Weiss, Rifkind, Wharton & Garrison LLP, Washington, DC, Sarah J. Prostko, Paul, Weiss, Rifkind, Wharton & Garrison LLP, New York, NY, for Respondents.

Admitted in Maryland and practicing law in the District of Columbia pending application for admission to the D.C. Bar under the supervision of bar members pursuant to D.C. Court of Appeals Rule 49(c)(8).

Justice SOTOMAYOR delivered the opinion of the Court. Like thousands of jurisdictions around the country, the City of Austin, Texas (City), regulates signs that advertise things that are not located on the same premises as the sign, as well as signs that direct people to offsite locations. These are known as off-premises signs, and they include, most notably, billboards. The question presented is whether, under this Court's precedents interpreting the Free Speech Clause of the First Amendment, the City's regulation is subject to strict scrutiny. We hold that it is not.

I

A

American jurisdictions have regulated outdoor advertisements for well over a century. See C. Taylor & W. Chang, The History of Outdoor Advertising Regulation in the United States, 15 J. of Macromarketing 47, 48 (Spring 1995). By some accounts, the proliferation of conspicuous patent-medicine advertisements on rocks and barns prompted States to begin regulating outdoor advertising in the late 1860s. Ibid. ; F. Presbrey, The History and Development of Advertising 500–501 (1929). As part of this regulatory tradition, federal, state, and local governments have long distinguished between signs (such as billboards) that promote ideas, products, or services located elsewhere and those that promote or identify things located onsite. For example, this Court in 1932 reviewed and approved of a Utah statute that prohibited signs advertising cigarettes and related products, but allowed businesses selling such products to post onsite signs identifying themselves as dealers. Packer Corp. v. Utah , 285 U.S. 105, 107, 110, 52 S.Ct. 273, 76 L.Ed. 643.

On-/off-premises distinctions, like the one at issue here, proliferated following the enactment of the Highway Beautification Act of 1965 (Act), 23 U.S.C. § 131. In the Act, Congress directed States receiving federal highway funding to regulate outdoor signs in proximity to federal highways, in part by limiting off-premises signs. See §§ 131(b) – (c) (allowing exceptions for "signs, displays, and devices advertising the sale or lease of property upon which they are located" and "signs, displays, and devices ... advertising activities conducted on the property on which they are located"). Under the Act, approximately two-thirds of States have implemented similar on-/off-premises distinctions. See App. A to Reply to Brief in Opposition (collecting statutes); Brief for State of Florida et al. as Amici Curiae 7, n. 3 (same). The City represents, and respondents have not disputed, that "tens of thousands of municipalities nationwide" have adopted analogous on-/off-premises distinctions in their sign codes. Brief for Petitioner 19; see also App. B to Reply to Brief in Opposition (collecting examples of ordinances); Brief for State of Florida et al. as Amici Curiae 8, n. 4 (same).

The City of Austin is one such municipality. The City distinguishes between on-premises and off-premises signs in its sign code, and specially regulates the latter, in order to "protect the aesthetic value of the city and to protect public safety." App. 39.

During the time period relevant to this dispute, the City's sign code defined the term "off-premise sign" to mean "a sign advertising a business, person, activity, goods, products, or services not located on the site where the sign is installed, or that directs persons to any location not on that site." Austin, Tex., City Code § 25–10–3(11) (2016). This definition was materially analogous to the one used in the federal Highway Beautification Act and many other state and local codes referenced above. The code prohibited the construction of any new off-premises signs, § 25–10–102(1), but allowed existing off-premises signs to remain as grandfathered "non-conforming signs," § 25–10–3(10). An owner of a grandfathered off-premises sign could "continue or maintain [it] at its existing location" and could change the "face of the sign," but could not "increase the degree of the existing nonconformity," "change the method or technology used to convey a message," or "increase the illumination of the sign." §§ 25–10–152(A)–(B). By contrast, the code permitted the digitization of on-premises signs. § 25–10–102(6) (permitting "electronically controlled changeable-copy sign[s]").

The City subsequently amended its sign code. The parties agree that the amendments do not affect this dispute. Reply to Brief in Opposition 11–12; Brief for Respondent Reagan 9.

B

Respondents, Reagan National Advertising of Austin, LLC (Reagan), and Lamar Advantage Outdoor Company, L. P. (Lamar), are outdoor-advertising companies that own billboards in Austin. In April and June of 2017, Reagan sought permits from the City to digitize some of its off-premises billboards. The City denied the applications. Reagan filed suit against the City in state court alleging that the code's prohibition against digitizing off-premises signs, but not on-premises signs, violated the Free Speech Clause of the First Amendment. The City removed the case to federal court, and Lamar intervened as a plaintiff.

Lamar did not participate in the proceedings on the merits before this Court. Brief for Respondent Reagan II.

After the parties stipulated to the pertinent facts, the District Court held a bench trial and entered judgment in favor of the City. 377 F.Supp.3d 670, 673, 683 (WD Tex. 2019). As relevant, the court held that the challenged sign code provisions were content neutral under Reed v. Town of Gilbert , 576 U.S. 155, 135 S.Ct. 2218, 192 L.Ed.2d 236 (2015). The court explained that "the on/off premises distinction [did] not impose greater restrictions for political messages, religious messages, or any other subject matter," and "d[id] not require a viewer to evaluate the topic, idea, or viewpoint on the sign"; instead, it required the viewer only "to determine whether the subject matter is located on the same property as the sign." 377 F.Supp.3d at 681. The court therefore held that the distinction was a facially content-neutral "regulation based on location." Ibid. The court further found "no evidence in the record" that the City had applied the sign code provisions "differently for different messages or speakers" or that its stated concern for esthetics and safety was "pretext for any other purpose." Id., at 681–682. Accordingly, the court reviewed the City's on-/off-premises distinction under the standard of intermediate scrutiny applicable to content-neutral regulations of speech. Id., at 682. The court found that the distinction satisfied this standard. Id., at 682–683.

The Court of Appeals reversed. 972 F.3d 696, 699 (CA5 2020). The court opined that because the City's on-/off-premises distinction required a reader to inquire "who is the speaker and what is the speaker saying," "both hallmarks of a content-based inquiry," the distinction was content based. Id., at 706. It reasoned that "[t]he fact that a government official ha[s] to read a sign's message to determine the sign's purpose [i]s enough to" render a regulation content based and "subject [it] to strict scrutiny." Ibid. (citing Thomas v. Bright , 937 F.3d 721, 730–731 (CA6 2019) ); see also 972 F.3d at 704 ("To determine whether a sign is on-premises or off-premises, one must read the sign ... "). The court acknowledged that its interpretation of Reed was "broad," but reasoned that the consequences were "not ... unforeseen," given the concerns raised by Justices who did not join the opinion of the Court. 972 F.3d at 707. Because the Court of Appeals determined that the City's on-/off-premises distinction imposed a content-based restriction on speech, it reviewed that distinction under the onerous standard of strict scrutiny. Recognizing that strict scrutiny "is, understandably, a hard standard to meet" and that it "leads to almost certain legal condemnation," id., at 709, the court held that the City's justifications for the distinction could not meet that standard, rendering it unconstitutional, id., at 709–710.

The Court of Appeals further considered the possibility that the code provisions regulated only commercial speech, such that only intermediate scrutiny would apply even if the provisions were content based. 972 F.3d at 707–709 ; see Central Hudson Gas & Elec. Corp. v. Public Serv. Comm'n of N. Y. , 447 U.S. 557, 566, 100 S.Ct. 2343, 65 L.Ed.2d 341 (1980). The court rejected this view because the provisions "applie[d] with equal force to both commercial and noncommercial messages." 972 F.3d at 709. Before this Court, the City makes a similar argument, claiming that "[a]s applied to billboards like those owned by respondents," the contested code provisions regulate commercial speech and so are subject to intermediate scrutiny. Brief for Petitioner 49. It is undisputed, however, that Reagan's billboards also display noncommercial messages, meaning that the City's denial of Reagan's applications for digitization implicated Reagan's commercial and noncommercial speech alike. See Brief for Respondent Reagan 45–46; App. 130–141. More importantly, as the Court of Appeals explained, the contested code provisions admit of no exception for noncommercial speech. The only way in which they differentiate speech is by distinguishing between on-premises and off-premises signs. The Court thus must determine which level of scrutiny applies to the manner in which the provisions actually regulate speech.

This Court granted certiorari. 594 U. S. ––––, 141 S.Ct. 2849, 210 L.Ed.2d 959 (2021).

II

A regulation of speech is facially content based under the First Amendment if it "target[s] speech based on its communicative content"—that is, if it "applies to particular speech because of the topic discussed or the idea or message expressed." Reed , 576 U.S. at 163, 135 S.Ct. 2218. The Court of Appeals interpreted Reed to mean that if "[a] reader must ask: who is the speaker and what is the speaker saying" to apply a regulation, then the regulation is automatically content based. 972 F.3d at 706. This rule, which holds that a regulation cannot be content neutral if it requires reading the sign at issue, is too extreme an interpretation of this Court's precedent. Unlike the regulations at issue in Reed , the City's off-premises distinction requires an examination of speech only in service of drawing neutral, location-based lines. It is agnostic as to content. Thus, absent a content-based purpose or justification, the City's distinction is content neutral and does not warrant the application of strict scrutiny.

A

The Reed Court confronted a very different regulatory scheme than the one at issue here: a comprehensive sign code that "single[d] out specific subject matter for differential treatment." 576 U.S. at 169, 135 S.Ct. 2218. The town of Gilbert, Arizona, had adopted a code that applied distinct size, placement, and time restrictions to 23 different categories of signs. Id., at 159, 135 S.Ct. 2218. The Court focused its analysis on three categories defined by whether the signs displayed ideological, political, or certain temporary directional messages. The code gave the most favorable treatment to " ‘Ideological Sign[s],’ " defined as those " ‘communicating a message or ideas for noncommercial purposes’ " with certain exceptions. Id., at 159–160, 135 S.Ct. 2218 (alteration in original). It offered less favorable treatment to " ‘Political Sign[s],’ " defined as those " ‘designed to influence the outcome of an election.’ " Id., at 160, 135 S.Ct. 2218 (alteration in original). Most restricted of all were " ‘Temporary Directional Signs Relating to a Qualifying Event,’ " with qualifying events defined as gatherings " ‘sponsored, arranged, or promoted by a religious, charitable, community service, educational, or other similar non-profit organization.’ " Id., at 160–161, 135 S.Ct. 2218.

The Reed Court determined that these restrictions were facially content based. Id., at 164–165, 135 S.Ct. 2218. Rejecting the contention that the restrictions were content neutral because they did not discriminate on the basis of viewpoint, the Court explained: "[I]t is well established that ‘[t]he First Amendment's hostility to content-based regulation extends not only to restrictions on particular viewpoints, but also to prohibition of public discussion of an entire topic.’ " Id., at 169, 135 S.Ct. 2218 (quoting Consolidated Edison Co. of N. Y. v. Public Serv. Comm'n of N. Y. , 447 U.S. 530, 537, 100 S.Ct. 2326, 65 L.Ed.2d 319 (1980) ); accord, e.g., Police Dept. of Chicago v. Mosley , 408 U.S. 92, 95, 92 S.Ct. 2286, 33 L.Ed.2d 212 (1972) (explaining that "[t]he central problem" with a municipality's effort to exempt labor picketing from a prohibition on picketing near public schools was "that it describes permissible picketing in terms of its subject matter"); Carey v. Brown , 447 U.S. 455, 460–461, 100 S.Ct. 2286, 65 L.Ed.2d 263 (1980) (subjecting a similar statute that "accord[ed] preferential treatment to the expression of views on one particular subject" to strict scrutiny). Applying these principles, the Court reasoned that "a speech regulation targeted at specific subject matter is content based even if it does not discriminate among viewpoints within that subject matter.... For example, a law banning the use of sound trucks for political speech—and only political speech—would be a content-based regulation, even if it imposed no limits on the political viewpoints that could be expressed." 576 U.S. at 169, 135 S.Ct. 2218. By treating ideological messages more favorably than political messages, and both more favorably than temporary directional messages, "[t]he Town's Sign Code likewise single[d] out specific subject matter for differential treatment, even if it [did] not target viewpoints within that subject matter." Ibid.

The concurrence in Reed , which spoke for three of the six Justices in the majority, similarly explained that "[c]ontent-based laws merit th[e] protection" of strict scrutiny "because they present, albeit sometimes in a subtler form, the same dangers as laws that regulate speech based on viewpoint. Limiting speech based on its ‘topic’ or ‘subject’ favors those who do not want to disturb the status quo. Such regulations may interfere with democratic self-government and the search for truth." 576 U.S. at 174, 135 S.Ct. 2218 (ALITO, J., concurring) (quoting Consolidated Edison Co. of N. Y. , 447 U.S. at 537, 100 S.Ct. 2326 ).

In this case, enforcing the City's challenged sign code provisions requires reading a billboard to determine whether it directs readers to the property on which it stands or to some other, offsite location. Unlike the sign code at issue in Reed , however, the City's provisions at issue here do not single out any topic or subject matter for differential treatment. A sign's substantive message itself is irrelevant to the application of the provisions; there are no content-discriminatory classifications for political messages, ideological messages, or directional messages concerning specific events, including those sponsored by religious and nonprofit organizations. Rather, the City's provisions distinguish based on location: A given sign is treated differently based solely on whether it is located on the same premises as the thing being discussed or not. The message on the sign matters only to the extent that it informs the sign's relative location. The on-/off-premises distinction is therefore similar to ordinary time, place, or manner restrictions. Reed does not require the application of strict scrutiny to this kind of location-based regulation. Cf. Frisby v. Schultz , 487 U.S. 474, 482, 108 S.Ct. 2495, 101 L.Ed.2d 420 (1988) (sustaining an ordinance that prohibited "only picketing focused on, and taking place in front of, a particular residence" as content neutral).

B

This Court's First Amendment precedents and doctrines have consistently recognized that restrictions on speech may require some evaluation of the speech and nonetheless remain content neutral.

Most relevant here, the First Amendment allows for regulations of solicitation—that is, speech "requesting or seeking to obtain something" or "[a]n attempt or effort to gain business." Black's Law Dictionary 1677 (11th ed. 2019). To identify whether speech entails solicitation, one must read or hear it first. Even so, the Court has reasoned that restrictions on solicitation are not content based and do not inherently present "the potential for becoming a means of suppressing a particular point of view," so long as they do not discriminate based on topic, subject matter, or viewpoint. Heffron v. International Soc. for Krishna Consciousness, Inc. , 452 U.S. 640, 649, 101 S.Ct. 2559, 69 L.Ed.2d 298 (1981).

Thus, in 1940, the Court invalidated a statute prohibiting solicitation for religious causes but observed that States were "free to regulate the time and manner of solicitation generally, in the interest of public safety, peace, comfort or convenience." Cantwell v. Connecticut , 310 U.S. 296, 306–307, 60 S.Ct. 900, 84 L.Ed. 1213. Decades later, the Court reviewed just such a time, place, and manner regulation restricting all solicitation at the Minnesota State Fair, as well as all sale or distribution of merchandise, to a specific location. Heffron , 452 U.S. at 643–644, 101 S.Ct. 2559. The State had applied the restriction against a religious practice that included "solicit[ing] donations for the support of the Krishna religion." Id., at 645, 101 S.Ct. 2559. As a result, members of the religion were free to roam the fairgrounds and discuss their beliefs, but they were prohibited from asking for donations for their cause outside of a designated location. Id., at 646, 655, 101 S.Ct. 2559. The Court upheld the State's application of this restriction as content neutral, emphasizing that it "applie[d] evenhandedly to all who wish[ed] ... to solicit funds," whether for "commercial or charitable" reasons. Id., at 649, 101 S.Ct. 2559.

Consistent with these precedents, the Court has previously understood distinctions between on-premises and off-premises signs, like the one at issue in this case, to be content neutral. In 1978, the Court summarily dismissed an appeal "for want of a substantial federal question" where a state court had approved of an on-/off-premises distinction as a permissible time, place, and manner restriction under the Free Speech Clause. Suffolk Outdoor Advertising Co. v. Hulse , 439 U.S. 808, 99 S.Ct. 66, 58 L.Ed.2d 101 (1978). Three years later, the Court upheld in relevant part an ordinance that prohibited all off-premises commercial advertising but allowed on-premises commercial advertising. Metromedia, Inc. v. San Diego , 453 U.S. 490, 503–512, 101 S.Ct. 2882, 69 L.Ed.2d 800 (1981) (plurality opinion). The Metromedia Court did not need to decide whether the off-premises prohibition was content based, as it regulated only commercial speech and so was subject to intermediate scrutiny in any event. See id., at 507–512, 101 S.Ct. 2882 (citing Central Hudson Gas & Elec. Corp. v. Public Serv. Comm'n of N. Y. , 447 U.S. 557, 100 S.Ct. 2343, 65 L.Ed.2d 341 (1980) ). Shortly thereafter, however, the Court applied the relevant portion of Metromedia and described the off-premises prohibition as "a content-neutral prohibition against the use of billboards." Members of City Council of Los Angeles v. Taxpayers for Vincent , 466 U.S. 789, 807, 104 S.Ct. 2118, 80 L.Ed.2d 772 (1984) (emphasis added).

Although the opinion in Metromedia was labeled a plurality for four Justices, the relevant portion of the opinion was also joined by a fifth. See 453 U.S. at 541, 101 S.Ct. 2882 (STEVENS, J., dissenting in part) ("join[ing] Parts I through IV of Justice WHITE's opinion").

Underlying these cases and others is a rejection of the view that any examination of speech or expression inherently triggers heightened First Amendment concern. Rather, it is regulations that discriminate based on "the topic discussed or the idea or message expressed" that are content based. Reed , 576 U.S. at 171, 135 S.Ct. 2218. The sign code provisions challenged here do not discriminate on those bases.

C

Reagan does not claim Reed expressly or implicitly overturned the precedents discussed above. Its argument relies primarily on one sentence in Reed recognizing that "[s]ome facial distinctions based on a message are obvious, defining regulated speech by particular subject matter, and others are more subtle, defining regulated speech by its function or purpose." Id., at 163, 135 S.Ct. 2218. Seizing on this reference, Reagan asserts that the City's sign code "defines off-premises signs based on their ‘function or purpose.’ " Brief for Respondent Reagan 20 (quoting Reed , 576 U.S. at 163, 135 S.Ct. 2218 ). It asks the Court to "reaffirm that, where a regulation ‘define[s] regulated speech by its function or purpose,’ it is content-based on its face and thus subject to strict scrutiny." Brief for Respondent Reagan 34 (quoting Reed , 576 U.S. at 163, 135 S.Ct. 2218 ).

The argument stretches Reed ’s "function or purpose" language too far. The principle the Reed Court articulated is more straightforward. While overt subject-matter discrimination is facially content based (for example, " ‘Ideological Sign[s],’ " defined as those " ‘communicating a message or ideas for noncommercial purposes’ "), so, too, are subtler forms of discrimination that achieve identical results based on function or purpose (for example, " ‘Political Sign[s],’ " defined as those " ‘designed to influence the outcome of an election’ "). Id., at 159, 160, 163–164, 135 S.Ct. 2218 (alterations in original). In other words, a regulation of speech cannot escape classification as facially content based simply by swapping an obvious subject-matter distinction for a "function or purpose" proxy that achieves the same result. That does not mean that any classification that considers function or purpose is always content based. Such a reading of "function or purpose" would contravene numerous precedents, including many of those discussed above. Reed did not purport to cast doubt on these cases.

Nor did Reed cast doubt on the Nation's history of regulating off-premises signs. Off-premises billboards of the sort that predominate today were not present in the founding era, but as large outdoor advertisements proliferated in the 1800s, regulation followed. As early as 1932, the Court had already approved a location-based differential for advertising signs. See Packer Corp. , 285 U.S. at 107, 110, 52 S.Ct. 273. Thereafter, for the last 50-plus years, federal, state, and local jurisdictions have repeatedly relied upon on-/off-premises distinctions to address the distinct safety and esthetic challenges posed by billboards and other methods of outdoor advertising. See supra, at 1469. The unbroken tradition of on-/off-premises distinctions counsels against the adoption of Reagan's novel rule. See Williams-Yulee v. Florida Bar , 575 U.S. 433, 446, 135 S.Ct. 1656, 191 L.Ed.2d 570 (2015) (recognizing "history and tradition of regulation" as relevant when considering the scope of the First Amendment).

The Court of Appeals, for its part, understood Reed to have deemed a regulation content based solely because "it ‘single[d] out signs bearing a particular message: the time and location of a specific event.’ " 972 F.3d 696, 706 (CA5 2020) (quoting Reed , 576 U.S. at 171, 135 S.Ct. 2218 ). Reagan does not rely as heavily on this language, and for good reason. As a preliminary matter, the Reed Court found that the provisions at issue in that case did not, in fact, "hinge on ‘whether and when an event is occurring.’ " Id., at 170, 135 S.Ct. 2218. More fundamentally, those provisions did not target all events generally, regardless of topic; they targeted "a specific event" (an election) "because of the topic discussed or the idea or message expressed" (political speech). Id., at 171, 135 S.Ct. 2218. The Court of Appeals’ contrary reading would render the majority opinion in Reed irreconcilable with the concurrence, which recognized that "[r]ules imposing time restrictions on signs advertising a one-time event," which "do not discriminate based on topic or subject," would be content neutral. Id., at 174, 175, 135 S.Ct. 2218 (ALITO, J., concurring).

D

Tellingly, even today's dissent appears reluctant to embrace the read-the-sign rule adopted by the court below. Instead, the dissent attacks a straw man. Contrary to its accusations, we do not "nullif[y]" Reed ’s protections, "resuscitat[e]" a decision that we do not cite, or fashion a novel "specificity test" simply by quoting the standard repeatedly enunciated in Reed . Post, at 1473, 1485 – 1486, 1487, 1492 (opinion of THOMAS, J.). Nor do we cast doubt on any of our precedents recognizing examples of topic or subject-matter discrimination as content based. See, e.g., post, at 1473 – 1474. We merely apply those precedents to reach the "commonsense" result that a location-based and content-agnostic on-/off-premises distinction does not, on its face, "singl[e] out specific subject matter for differential treatment." Reed , 576 U.S. at 163, 169, 135 S.Ct. 2218.

It is the dissent that would upend settled understandings of the law. Where we adhere to the teachings of history, experience, and precedent, the dissent would hold that tens of thousands of jurisdictions have presumptively violated the First Amendment, some for more than half a century, and that they have done so by use of an on-/off-premises distinction this Court has repeatedly reviewed and never previously questioned. For the reasons we have explained, the Constitution does not require that bizarre result.

III

This Court's determination that the City's ordinance is facially content neutral does not end the First Amendment inquiry. If there is evidence that an impermissible purpose or justification underpins a facially content-neutral restriction, for instance, that restriction may be content based. See Reed , 576 U.S. at 164, 135 S.Ct. 2218. Moreover, to survive intermediate scrutiny, a restriction on speech or expression must be " ‘narrowly tailored to serve a significant governmental interest.’ " Ward v. Rock Against Racism , 491 U.S. 781, 791, 109 S.Ct. 2746, 105 L.Ed.2d 661 (1989).

The parties dispute whether the City can satisfy these requirements. This Court, however, is "a court of final review and not first view," and it does not "[o]rdinarily ... decide in the first instance issues not decided below." Zivotofsky v. Clinton , 566 U.S. 189, 201, 132 S.Ct. 1421, 182 L.Ed.2d 423 (2012) (internal quotation marks omitted). "In particular, when we reverse on a threshold question, we typically remand for resolution of any claims the lower courts’ error prevented them from addressing." Ibid. Because the Court of Appeals did not address these issues, the Court leaves them for remand and expresses no view on the matters.

* * *

For these reasons, the judgment of the Court of Appeals for the Fifth Circuit is reversed, and the case is remanded for further proceedings consistent with this opinion.

It is so ordered.

Justice BREYER, concurring.

Reed v. Town of Gilbert , 576 U.S. 155, 135 S.Ct. 2218, 192 L.Ed.2d 236 (2015), is binding precedent here. Given that precedent, I join the majority's opinion. I write separately because I continue to believe that the Court's reasoning in Reed was wrong. The Court there struck down a city's sign ordinance under the First Amendment. It wrote that the First Amendment requires strict scrutiny whenever a regulation "target[s] speech based on its communicative content." Id., at 163, 135 S.Ct. 2218. It therefore concluded that "[c]ontent-based laws ... are presumptively unconstitutional and may be justified only if the government proves that they are narrowly tailored to serve compelling state interests." Ibid.

But the First Amendment is not the Tax Code. Its purposes are often better served when judge-made categories (like "content discrimination") are treated, not as bright-line rules, but instead as rules of thumb. And, where strict scrutiny's harsh presumption of unconstitutionality is at issue, it is particularly important to avoid jumping to such presumptive conclusions without first considering "whether the regulation at issue works harm to First Amendment interests that is disproportionate in light of the relevant regulatory objectives." Id., at 179, 135 S.Ct. 2218 (BREYER, J., concurring in judgment); Barr v. American Assn. of Political Consultants, Inc. , 591 U. S. ––––, –––– – ––––, 140 S.Ct. 2335, 2361-2362, 207 L.Ed.2d 784 (2020) (BREYER, J., concurring in judgment and dissenting in part); Sorrell v. IMS Health Inc. , 564 U.S. 552, 582, 131 S.Ct. 2653, 180 L.Ed.2d 544 (2011) (BREYER, J., dissenting). Here, I would conclude that the City of Austin's (City's) regulation of off-premises signs works no such disproportionate harm. I therefore agree with the majority's conclusion that strict scrutiny and its attendant presumption of unconstitutionality are unwarranted. The majority reaches this conclusion by applying Reed ’s formal framework, as stare decisis requires. I would add that Reed ’s strict formalism can sometimes disserve the very First Amendment interests it was designed to protect.

I

The First Amendment helps to safeguard what Justice HOLMES described as a marketplace of ideas. Abrams v. United States , 250 U.S. 616, 630, 40 S.Ct. 17, 63 L.Ed. 1173 (1919) (dissenting opinion). A democratic people must be able to freely "generate, debate, and discuss both general and specific ideas, hopes, and experiences." Barr , 591 U. S., at ––––, 140 S.Ct., at 2358 (opinion of BREYER, J.). They "must then be able to transmit their resulting views and conclusions to their elected representatives, which they may do directly, or indirectly through the shaping of public opinion." Ibid. Those representatives can respond by turning the people's ideas into policies. The First Amendment, by protecting the "marketplace" and the "transmission" of ideas, thereby helps to protect the basic workings of democracy itself. See Meyer v. Grant , 486 U.S. 414, 421, 108 S.Ct. 1886, 100 L.Ed.2d 425 (1988) ("The First Amendment was ‘fashioned to assure unfettered interchange of ideas for the bringing about of political and social changes desired by the people’ ").

Courts help to protect these democratic values in part by strictly scrutinizing certain categories of laws that threaten to " ‘drive certain ideas or viewpoints from the marketplace.’ " R. A. V. v. St. Paul , 505 U.S. 377, 387, 112 S.Ct. 2538, 120 L.Ed.2d 305 (1992). We have recognized, for example, that First Amendment values are in danger when the government imposes restrictions upon " ‘core political speech,’ " Buckley v. American Constitutional Law Foundation, Inc. , 525 U.S. 182, 186–187, 119 S.Ct. 636, 142 L.Ed.2d 599 (1999) ; when it discriminates against "particular views taken by speakers on a subject," Rosenberger v. Rector and Visitors of Univ. of Va. , 515 U.S. 819, 829–830, 115 S.Ct. 2510, 132 L.Ed.2d 700 (1995) ; and, in some contexts, when it removes "an entire topic" of discussion from public debate, Consolidated Edison Co. of N. Y. v. Public Serv. Comm'n of N. Y. , 447 U.S. 530, 537–538, 100 S.Ct. 2326, 65 L.Ed.2d 319 (1980).

But not all laws that distinguish between speech based on its content fall into a category of this kind. That is in part because many ordinary regulatory programs may well turn on the content of speech without posing any "realistic possibility that official suppression of ideas is afoot." R. A. V. , 505 U.S. at 390, 112 S.Ct. 2538. Those regulations, rather than hindering the ability of the people to transmit their thoughts to their elected representatives, may constitute the very product of that transmission. Barr , 591 U. S., at ––––, 140 S.Ct., at 2358-2359 (opinion of BREYER, J.).

The U. S. Code (as well as its state and local equivalents) is filled with regulatory laws that turn, often necessarily, on the content of speech. Consider laws regulating census reporting requirements, e.g., 13 U.S.C. § 224 ; securities-related disclosures, e.g., 15 U.S.C. § 78l ; copyright infringement, e.g., 17 U.S.C. § 102 ; labeling of prescription drugs, e.g., 21 U.S.C. § 353(b)(4)(A), or consumer electronics, e.g., 42 U.S.C. § 6294 ; highway signs, e.g., 23 U.S.C. § 131(c) ; tax disclosures, e.g., 26 U.S.C. § 6039F ; confidential medical records, e.g., 38 U.S.C. § 7332 ; robocalls, e.g., 47 U.S.C. § 227 ; workplace safety warnings, e.g., 29 C.F.R. § 1910.145 (2021) ; panhandling, e.g., Ala. Code § 13A–11–9(a) (2022) ; solicitation on behalf of charities, e.g., N. Y. Exec. Law Ann. § 174–b (West 2019); signs at petting zoos, e.g., N. Y. Gen. Bus. Law Ann. § 399–ff(3) (West 2015); and many more.

If Reed is taken as setting forth a formal rule that courts must strictly scrutinize regulations simply because they refer to particular content, we have good reason to fear the consequences of that decision. One possibility is that courts will strike down " ‘entirely reasonable’ " regulations that reflect the will of the people. Reed , 576 U.S. at 171, 135 S.Ct. 2218 ; e.g., Barr , 591 U. S., at ––––, 140 S.Ct., at 2361-2362 (striking down the Telephone Consumer Protection Act's exception allowing robocalls that collect government debt); IMDB.com v. Becerra , 962 F.3d 1111, 1125–1127 (CA9 2020) (striking down a California law prohibiting certain websites from publishing the birthdates of entertainment professionals). If so, the Court's content-based line-drawing will "substitut[e] judicial for democratic decisionmaking" and threaten the ability of the people to translate their ideas into policy. Sorrell , 564 U.S. at 603, 131 S.Ct. 2653 (BREYER, J., dissenting).

A second possibility is that courts instead will (perhaps unconsciously) dilute the stringent strict scrutiny standard in an effort to avoid striking down reasonable regulations. Doing so would "weaken the First Amendment's protection in instances where ‘strict scrutiny’ should apply in full force." Reed , 576 U.S. at 178, 135 S.Ct. 2218 (opinion of BREYER, J.).

A third possibility is that courts will develop a matrix of formal subsidiary rules and exceptions that seek to distinguish between reasonable and unreasonable content-based regulations. Such a patchwork, however, may prove overly complex, unwieldy, or unworkable. And it may make it more difficult for ordinary Americans to understand the importance of First Amendment values and to live their lives in accord with those values.

For these reasons, as I have said before, I would reject Reed's approach, which too rigidly ties content discrimination to strict scrutiny (and, consequently, to "almost certain legal condemnation"). Id. , at 176, 135 S.Ct. 2218. Instead, I would treat content discrimination as a rule of thumb to be applied with what Justice KAGAN has called "a dose of common sense." Id., at 183, 135 S.Ct. 2218 (opinion concurring in judgment). Where content-based regulations are at issue, I would ask a more basic First Amendment question: Does "the regulation at issue wor[k] harm to First Amendment interests that is disproportionate in light of the relevant regulatory objectives"? Id., at 179, 135 S.Ct. 2218 (opinion of BREYER, J.). I believe we should answer that question by examining "the seriousness of the harm to speech, the importance of the countervailing objectives, the extent to which the law will achieve those objectives, and whether there are other, less restrictive ways of doing so." Ibid.

II

The regulation at issue in this case is the City of Austin's sign code, which regulates billboards and other "off-premises" signs. The City defines an "off-premises" sign as "a sign advertising a business, person, activity, goods, products, or services not located on the site where the sign is installed, or that directs persons to any location not on that site." Austin, Tex., City Code § 25–10–3(11) (2016).

Some years ago, the City forbid construction of new off-premises signs. § 25–10–102(1). At the same time, it grandfathered in existing off-premises signs, allowing them to remain but subjecting them to regulation. §§ 25–10–3(10), 25–10–152(A), (B). Owners of grandfathered off-premises signs are allowed to change the face of their signs, but not to digitize them. Ibid. In the case before us, owners who wanted to digitize their off-premises signs challenged the City's regulation on the ground that it violates the First Amendment.

The Court remands for the lower courts to assess the constitutionality of this regulation in the first instance, so I need not answer that question conclusively now. I wish only to illustrate why I believe a strong presumption of unlawfulness is out of place here.

Billboards and other roadside signs can generally be categorized as a form of outdoor advertising. Regulation of outdoor advertising in order to protect the public's interest in "avoiding visual clutter," Members of City Council of Los Angeles v. Taxpayers for Vincent , 466 U.S. 789, 806, 104 S.Ct. 2118, 80 L.Ed.2d 772 (1984), or minimizing traffic risks, Metromedia, Inc. v. San Diego , 453 U.S. 490, 507–508, 101 S.Ct. 2882, 69 L.Ed.2d 800 (1981), is unlikely to interfere significantly with the "marketplace of ideas." In this case, for example, there is no evidence that the City regulated off-premises signs in order to censor a particular viewpoint or topic, or that its regulations have had that effect in practice. There is consequently little reason to apply a presumption of unconstitutionality to this kind of regulation.

Without such a presumption, I would weigh the First Amendment harms that a regulation imposes against the regulatory objectives that it serves. The City's regulation here appears to work at most a limited, niche-like harm to First Amendment interests. Respondents own a number of grandfathered off-premises signs. They can use those signs to communicate whatever messages they choose. They complain only that they cannot digitize the signs, which would allow them to display several messages in rapid succession. Perhaps digitization would enable them to make more effective use of their billboard space. But their inability to maximize the use of their space in this way is unlikely to meaningfully interfere with their participation in the "marketplace of ideas."

At the same time, the City has asserted a legitimate interest in maintaining the regulation. As I have said, the public has an interest in ensuring traffic safety and preserving an esthetically pleasing environment, supra this page, and the City here has reasonably explained how its regulation of off-premises signs in general, and digitization in particular, serves those interests. Amici tell us that billboards, especially digital ones, can distract drivers and cause accidents. See, e.g., Brief for United States as Amicus Curiae 21 (citing a study of 450 crashes in Alabama and Florida that "revealed that the presence of digital billboards increased the overall crash rates in areas of billboard influence"); Brief for National League of Cities et al. as Amici Curiae 22 (" ‘The Wisconsin Department of Transport found a 35% increase in collisions near a variable message sign’ " (alteration omitted)). They add that on-premises signs are less likely to cause accidents. Id., at 23 ("[A] 2014 study found no evidence that on premises digital signs led to an increase in crashes"). The City further says that billboards cause more visual clutter than on-premises signs because the latter are "typically ‘small in size’ and integrated into the premises." Reply Brief 19.

I would leave for the courts below to weigh these harms and interests, and any alternatives, in the first instance, without a strong presumption of unconstitutionality.

Justice ALITO, concurring in the judgment in part and dissenting in part.

I agree with the majority that we must reverse the decision of the Court of Appeals holding that the provisions of the Austin City Code regulating on- and off-premises signs are facially unconstitutional. Ante , at 1471 – 1472. The Court of Appeals reasoned that those provisions impose content-based restrictions and that they cannot satisfy strict scrutiny, but the Court of Appeals did not apply the tests that must be met before a law is held to be facially unconstitutional. "Normally, a plaintiff bringing a facial challenge must ‘establish that no set of circumstances exists under which the [law] would be valid,’ or show that the law lacks ‘a plainly legitimate sweep.’ " Americans for Prosperity Foundation v. Bonta , 594 U. S. ––––, ––––, 141 S.Ct. 2373, 2387, 210 L.Ed.2d 716 (2021) (citation omitted). A somewhat less demanding test applies when a law affects freedom of speech. Under our First Amendment "overbreadth" doctrine, a law restricting speech is unconstitutional "if a substantial number of its applications are unconstitutional, judged in relation to the statute's plainly legitimate sweep." United States v. Stevens , 559 U.S. 460, 473, 130 S.Ct. 1577, 176 L.Ed.2d 435 (2010) (internal quotation marks omitted).

In this case, the Court of Appeals did not apply either of those tests, and it is doubtful that they can be met. Many (and possibly the great majority) of the situations in which the relevant provisions may apply involve commercial speech, and under our precedents, regulations of commercial speech are analyzed differently. See Sorrell v. IMS Health Inc. , 564 U.S. 552, 571–572, 131 S.Ct. 2653, 180 L.Ed.2d 544 (2011).

It is also questionable whether those code provisions are unconstitutional as applied to most of respondents’ billboards. It appears that most if not all of those billboards are located off-premises in both the usual sense of that term, and in the sense in which the term is used in the Austin code. See Austin, Tex., City Code § 25–10–3(11) (2016) (a sign is off-premises if it "advertis[es] a business, person, activity, goods, products, or services not located on the site where the sign is installed" or if it "directs persons to any location not on that site"). The record contains photos of some of these billboards, see App. 130–147, and all but one appears to be located on otherwise vacant land. Thus, they are clearly off-premises signs, and because they were erected before the enactment of the code provisions at issue, the only relevant restriction they face is that they cannot be digitized. The distinction between a digitized and non-digitized sign is not based on content, topic, or subject matter. Even if the message on a billboard were written in a secret code, an observer would have no trouble determining whether it had been digitized.

In ordinary usage, a sign that is attached to or located in close proximity to a building is not described as located "off-premises." The distinction between on- and off-premises signs is based solely on location, and that is why such a classification is not content-based. See Reed v. Town of Gilbert , 576 U.S. 155, 175, 135 S.Ct. 2218, 192 L.Ed.2d 236 (2015) (ALITO, J., concurring).

For several categories of historically unprotected speech, including obscenity, defamation, fraud, incitement, and speech integral to criminal conduct, the government ordinarily may enact content-based restrictions without satisfying strict scrutiny. See United States v. Stevens , 559 U.S. 460, 468–469, 130 S.Ct. 1577, 176 L.Ed.2d 435 (2010). This Court's precedents have also declined to apply strict scrutiny to several other types of content-based restrictions, including laws targeting "commercial speech." Central Hudson Gas & Elec. Corp. v. Public Serv. Comm'n of N. Y. , 447 U.S. 557, 561–566, 100 S.Ct. 2343, 65 L.Ed.2d 341 (1980). But see Lorillard Tobacco Co. v. Reilly , 533 U.S. 525, 572, 121 S.Ct. 2404, 150 L.Ed.2d 532 (2001) (THOMAS, J., concurring in part and concurring in judgment). As the Court recognizes, Austin's off-premises sign rule is not limited to any of these categories of speech. See ante, at 1471, n. 3.

A grandfathered sign can be maintained at its existing location, but the owner cannot "increase the degree of the existing nonconformity," "change the method or technology used to convey a message," or "increase the illumination of the sign." Austin, Tex., City Code §§ 25–10–152(A)–(B).

In Reed , we acknowledged that some prior decisions had skipped over this facial analysis and applied a justification-focused test. See 576 U.S. at 165–167, 135 S.Ct. 2218. But we explained that the justification-focused test implicated a "separate and additional category of laws that, though facially content neutral, [are] content-based regulations [because they] cannot be ‘ "justified without reference to the content of the regulated speech," ’ or ... were adopted by the government ‘because of disagreement with the message [the speech] conveys.’ " Id., at 164, 135 S.Ct. 2218 (quoting Ward v. Rock Against Racism , 491 U.S. 781, 791, 109 S.Ct. 2746, 105 L.Ed.2d 661 (1989) ). All agree that this second type of content-based regulation is not at issue here.

Because the Court of Appeals erred in holding that the code provisions are facially unconstitutional, I agree that we should reverse that decision. On remand, the lower courts should determine whether those provisions are unconstitutional as applied to each of the billboards at issue.

Today's decision, however, goes further and holds flatly that "[t]he sign code provisions challenged here do not discriminate" on the basis of " ‘the topic discussed or the idea or message expressed,’ " ante , at 1474, and that categorical statement is incorrect. The provisions defining on- and off-premises signs clearly discriminate on those grounds, and at least as applied in some situations, strict scrutiny should be required.

As the Court notes, under the provisions in effect when petitioner's applications were denied, a sign was considered to be off-premises if it "advertis[ed]," among other things, a "person, activity, ... or servic[e] not located on the site where the sign is installed" or if it "direct[ed] persons to any location not on that site." Austin, Tex., City Code § 25–10–3(11). Consider what this definition would mean as applied to signs posted in the front window of a commercial establishment, say, a little coffee shop. If the owner put up a sign advertising a new coffee drink, the sign would be classified as on-premises, but suppose the owner instead mounted a sign in the same location saying: "Contribute to X's legal defense fund" or "Free COVID tests available at Y pharmacy" or "Attend City Council meeting to speak up about Z." All those signs would appear to fall within the definition of an off-premises sign and would thus be disallowed. See also post , at 3–4 (THOMAS, J., dissenting). Providing disparate treatment for the sign about a new drink and the signs about social and political matters constitutes discrimination on the basis of topic or subject matter. The code provisions adopted in 2017 are worded differently, but the new wording may not rule out similar results.

The amended code now defines "off-premise[s] sign" as "a sign that displays any message directing attention to a business, product, service, profession, commodity, activity, event, person, institution, or other commercial message which is generally conducted, sold, manufactured, produced, offered, or occurs elsewhere than on the premises where the sign is located," and defines an "on-premise[s] sign" as "a sign that is not an off-premise[s] sign." Austin, Tex., City Code §§ 25–10–4(9)–(10) (2021). It is not clear that the inclusion of "other commercial message" modifies the terms "activity," "event," "person," or "institution" such that the provision would not draw topic-based distinctions as applied to non-commercial speech.

On this point, the majority's analysis tracks the position advanced by Austin, which asserted that content neutrality was a "question of generality." Tr. of Oral Arg. 14; see also id., at 19 (explaining that whether a law is content based turns on the "level of specificity" at which the government regulates speech).

For these reasons, I would simply hold that the provisions at issue are not facially unconstitutional, and I would refrain from making any broader pronouncements.

Justice THOMAS, with whom Justice GORSUCH and Justice BARRETT join, dissenting.

In Reed v. Town of Gilbert , 576 U.S. 155, 135 S.Ct. 2218, 192 L.Ed.2d 236 (2015), we held that a speech regulation is content based—and thus presumptively invalid—if it "draws distinctions based on the message a speaker conveys." Id. , at 163, 135 S.Ct. 2218. Here, the city of Austin imposes special restrictions on "off-premise[s] sign[s]," defined as signs that "advertis[e] a business, person, activity, goods, products, or services not located on the site where the sign is installed, or that direc[t] persons to any location not on that site." Austin, Tex., City Code § 25–10–3(11) (2016). Under Reed , Austin's off-premises restriction is content based. It discriminates against certain signs based on the message they convey—e.g. , whether they promote an on- or off-site event, activity, or service.

The Court nevertheless holds that the off-premises restriction is content neutral because it proscribes a sufficiently broad category of communicative content and, therefore, does not target a specific "topic or subject matter." Ante , at 1472. This misinterprets Reed ’s clear rule for content-based restrictions and replaces it with an incoherent and malleable standard. In so doing, the majority's reasoning is reminiscent of this Court's erroneous decision in Hill v. Colorado , 530 U.S. 703, 120 S.Ct. 2480, 147 L.Ed.2d 597 (2000), which upheld a blatantly content-based prohibition on "counseling" near abortion clinics on the ground that it discriminated against "an extremely broad category of communications." Id. , at 723, 120 S.Ct. 2480. Because I would adhere to Reed rather than echo Hill ’s long-discredited approach, I respectfully dissent.

I

A

The First Amendment, applicable to the States through the Fourteenth, prohibits laws "abridging the freedom of speech." U. S. Const., Amdt. 1; see also Stromberg v. California , 283 U.S. 359, 368, 51 S.Ct. 532, 75 L.Ed. 1117 (1931). "When enforcing this prohibition, our precedents distinguish between content-based and content-neutral regulations." National Institute of Family and Life Advocates v. Becerra , 585 U. S. ––––, ––––, 138 S.Ct. 2361, 2371, 201 L.Ed.2d 835 (2018). A content-based law is "presumptively invalid," United States v. Playboy Entertainment Group, Inc. , 529 U.S. 803, 817, 120 S.Ct. 1878, 146 L.Ed.2d 865 (2000) (internal quotation marks omitted), and may generally be upheld only if the government proves that the regulation is narrowly tailored to serve compelling state interests, R. A. V. v. St. Paul , 505 U.S. 377, 395, 112 S.Ct. 2538, 120 L.Ed.2d 305 (1992).1

In Reed v. Town of Gilbert , we held that courts should identify content-based restrictions by applying a "commonsense" test: A speech regulation is content based if it "target[s] speech based on its communicative content." 576 U.S. at 163, 135 S.Ct. 2218. Put another way, a law is content based " ‘on its face’ [if it] draws distinctions based on the message a speaker conveys." Ibid. While we noted that "[s]ome facial distinctions based on a message are obvious," we emphasized that others could be "more subtle, defining regulated speech by its function or purpose." Ibid . In all events, whether a law is characterized as targeting a "topic," "idea," "subject matter," or "communicative content," the law is content based if it draws distinctions based in any way "on the message a speaker conveys." Id. , at 163–164, 135 S.Ct. 2218.2

Applying this standard, we held that the town of Gilbert's sign code was "a paradigmatic example of content-based discrimination" because it classified "various categories of signs based on the type of information they convey[ed], [and] then subject[ed] each category to different restrictions." Id. , at 169, 159, 135 S.Ct. 2218. For instance, Gilbert defined " ‘Temporary Directional Signs’ " as any sign that "convey[ed] the message of directing the public to [a] ‘qualifying event,’ " and permitted their display for no more than 12 hours before and 1 hour after the event occurred. Id. , at 164, 161, 135 S.Ct. 2218. Meanwhile, " ‘Ideological Sign[s],’ " defined as any sign (not covered by another category) that " ‘communicat[ed] a message or ideas for noncommercial purposes,’ " were subject to no temporal limitations. Id. , at 159–160, 135 S.Ct. 2218. In short, the restrictions on any given sign depended "on the communicative content of the sign." Id. , at 164, 135 S.Ct. 2218. Gilbert's sign code was thus facially content based and presumptively unlawful. See id. , at 159, 135 S.Ct. 2218.

In contrast to Reed ’s "commonsense" test, Gilbert urged us to define "content based" as a "term of art that ‘should be applied flexibly’ with the goal of protecting ‘viewpoints and ideas from government censorship or favoritism.’ " Id. , at 168, 135 S.Ct. 2218. Such a functionalist test, Gilbert argued, could ferret out illicit government motives while obviating the need to subject reasonable laws to strict scrutiny. See ibid. We rejected Gilbert's attempt to cast the phrase "content based" as a "term of art" because "[i]nnocent motives do not eliminate the danger of censorship presented by a facially content-based statute." Id. , at 167, 135 S.Ct. 2218. We noted that "one could easily imagine a Sign Code compliance manager who disliked [a] Church's substantive teachings deploying the Sign Code to make it more difficult for the Church to inform the public of the location of its services." Id. , at 167–168, 135 S.Ct. 2218. Thus, we concluded that "a clear and firm rule governing content neutrality is an essential means of protecting the freedom of speech, even if laws that might seem entirely reasonable will sometimes be struck down because of their content-based nature." Id. , at 171, 135 S.Ct. 2218 (internal quotation marks omitted).

We also rejected the Ninth Circuit's reasoning that Gilbert's sign restrictions were content neutral because they depended on "the content-neutral elements of ... whether and when an event is occurring." Id. , at 169, 135 S.Ct. 2218 (internal quotation marks omitted). That is, whether a temporary directional sign was permissible depended, in part, on its temporal proximity to a " ‘qualifying event.’ " Id. , at 164, 135 S.Ct. 2218. This partial dependence on content-neutral elements was immaterial, we explained, because the restrictions also depended on the signs’ communicative content. Gilbert officials still had to examine a sign's message to determine what type of sign it was, and this "obvious content-based inquiry d[id] not evade strict scrutiny simply because an event [was] involved." Id. , at 170, 135 S.Ct. 2218.

B

Under Reed ’s approach for identifying content-based regulations, Austin's off-premises sign restriction is content based. As relevant to this suit, Austin's sign code imposes stringent restrictions on a category of "off-premise[s] sign[s]." § 25–10–3(11). The code defines "off-premise[s] sign[s]" as those "advertising a business, person, activity, goods, products, or services not located on the site where the sign is installed," or as signs "direct[ing] persons to any location not on that site." Ibid. This broad definition sweeps in a wide swath of signs, from 14- by 48-foot billboards to 24- by 18-inch yard signs. The sign code prohibits new off-premises signs and makes it difficult (or impossible) to change existing off-premises signs, including by digitizing them. See ante , at 1469 – 1470.

Like the town of Gilbert in Reed , Austin has identified a "categor[y] of signs based on the type of information they convey, [and] then subject[ed that] category to different restrictions." 576 U.S. at 159, 135 S.Ct. 2218. A sign that conveys a message about off-premises activities is restricted, while one that conveys a message about on-premises activities is not. See id. , at 171, 135 S.Ct. 2218 (regulating signs based on "a particular message" about "the time and location of a specific event" is content based). And, per Reed , it does not matter that Austin's code "defin[es] regulated speech by its function or purpose"—i.e. , advertising or directing passersby elsewhere. Id. , at 163, 135 S.Ct. 2218. Again, all that matters is that the regulation "draws distinctions based on" a sign's "communicative content," which the off-premises restriction plainly does. Ibid .

This conclusion is not undermined because the off-premises sign restriction depends in part on a content-neutral element: the location of the sign. Much like in Reed , that an Austin official applying the sign code must know where the sign is does not negate the fact that he also must know what the sign says. Take, for instance, a sign outside a Catholic bookstore. If the sign says, "Visit the Holy Land," it is likely an off-premises sign because it conveys a message directing people elsewhere (unless the name of the bookstore is "Holy Land Books"). But if the sign instead says, "Buy More Books," it is likely a permissible on-premises sign (unless the sign also contains the address of another bookstore across town). Finally, suppose the sign says, "Go to Confession." After examining the sign's message, an official would need to inquire whether a priest ever hears confessions at that location. If one does, the sign could convey a permissible "on-premises" message. If not, the sign conveys an impermissible off-premises message. Because enforcing the sign code in any of these instances "requires [Austin] officials to determine whether a sign" conveys a particular message, the sign code is content based under Reed . Id. , at 170, 135 S.Ct. 2218.

In sum, the off-premises rule is content based and thus invalid unless Austin can satisfy strict scrutiny. See Playboy Entertainment Group , 529 U.S. at 813, 120 S.Ct. 1878. Because Austin has offered nothing to make that showing, the Court of Appeals did not err in holding that the off-premises rule violates the First Amendment.

II

To reach the opposite result, the majority implicitly rewrites Reed ’s bright-line rule for content-based restrictions. In the majority's view, the off-premises restriction is not content based because it does not target a specific "topic or subject matter." Ante , at 1472. The upshot of the majority's reasoning appears to be that a regulation based on a sufficiently general or broad category of communicative content is not actually content based.

Such a rule not only conflicts with Reed and many pre- Reed precedents but is also incoherent and unworkable. Tellingly, the only decision that even remotely supports the majority's rule is one it does not cite: Hill v. Colorado . There, the Court held that an undeniably content-based law was nonetheless content neutral because it discriminated against "an extremely broad category of communications," supposedly without regard to "subject matter." 530 U.S. at 723, 120 S.Ct. 2480. The majority's decision today is erroneous for the same reasons that Hill is an aberration in our case law.

A

The majority concedes that "[t]he message on the sign matters" when applying Austin's sign code. Ante , at 1472. That concession should end the inquiry under Reed . But the majority nonetheless finds the sign code to be content neutral by recasting facially content-based restrictions as only those that target sufficiently specific categories of communicative content and not as those that depend on communicative content simpliciter . For example, while Reed defined content-based restrictions as those that "dra[w] distinctions based on the message a speaker conveys," 576 U.S. at 163, 135 S.Ct. 2218 (emphasis added), the majority decides that Austin's sign code is not content based because it draws no distinctions based on "[a] sign's substantive message," ante , at 1472 (emphasis added). Elsewhere, the majority speaks not of "substantive message[s]" but of "topic[s] or subject matter[s]," which the majority thinks are sufficiently specific categories of communicative content. Ibid. As a result, the majority contends that a law targeting directional messages concerning "events generally, regardless of topic," would not be content based, but one targeting "directional messages concerning specific events" (e.g. , "religious" or "political" events) would be. Ante , at 1475, n. 6, 1472 (emphasis added).3 Regardless of the label, the majority today excises, without a word of explanation, a subset of supposedly non-substantive or unspecific messages from the First Amendment's protection against content-based restrictions.

This understanding of content-based restrictions contravenes Reed , which held that a law is content based if it "target[s] speech based on its communicative content"—not "specific" or "substantive" categories of communicative content. 576 U.S. at 163, 135 S.Ct. 2218 ; see also, e.g. , Norton v. Springfield , 806 F.3d 411, 412 (CA7 2015) (" Reed effectively abolishes any distinction between content regulation and subject-matter regulation. Any law distinguishing one kind of speech from another by reference to its meaning now requires a compelling justification"). Only by jettisoning Reed ’s "commonsense" definition of what it means to be content based can the majority assert that the off-premises rule is strictly "location-based" and "agnostic as to content," ante , at 1471, even though the law undeniably depends on both location and communicative content, supra , at 1470 – 1471.

Moreover, the majority's suggestion that laws targeting broad categories of communicative content are not content based is hard to square with the sign categories that Reed invalidated. For instance, we found Gilbert's expansive definition of "Ideological Sign[s]" to be content based even though it broadly covered any "sign communicating a message or ideas for noncommercial purposes" that did not already fall into one of the other categories. 576 U.S. at 159, 135 S.Ct. 2218 (internal quotation marks omitted). Nor did we suggest that the outcome in Reed would have been different if the sign categories were defined even more generally.

The majority answers that it is not "fashion[ing] a novel ‘specificity test,’ " but instead "simply" "quoting the standard repeatedly enunciated in Reed ." Ante , at 1475. The majority finds this alleged specificity test in a paragraph near the end of Reed , where we noted that a law "targeted at specific subject matter is content based even if it does not discriminate among viewpoints within that subject matter," and then affirmed that Gilbert's sign code "single[d] out specific subject matter for differential treatment." 576 U.S. at 169, 135 S.Ct. 2218.

These statements never purported to endorse a specificity test of the sort now suggested by the majority. Read in context, Reed ’s two references to "specific subject matter" naturally address laws that target a "subject matter," however broadly defined, as opposed to some other subject matter; they did not refer only to laws targeting some sufficiently "specific" category of "subject matter." Moreover, the concept of "specificity" or "generality" appears nowhere in the part of Reed that set forth its "commonsense" test for content neutrality. See id. , at 163–164, 135 S.Ct. 2218. If Reed ’s content-neutrality test turned on specificity, we would have said so explicitly when stating the test. Finally, even crediting the majority's strained reading of Reed ’s passing references to "specific subject matter," the paragraph where they appear made clear that it was describing only "a paradigmatic example of content-based discrimination." Id. , at 169, 135 S.Ct. 2218 (emphasis added). That part of Reed never professed to announce a comprehensive rule with respect to all laws targeting speech based on its communicative content.

Our pre- Reed precedents likewise foreclose a construction of "content based" that applies only to some content. We have held many capacious speech regulations to be content based, including restrictions on " ‘advice or assistance derived from scientific, technical or other specialized knowledge,’ " Holder v. Humanitarian Law Project , 561 U.S. 1, 12–13, 130 S.Ct. 2705, 177 L.Ed.2d 355 (2010) ; " ‘advertising, promotion, or any activity ... used to influence sales or the market share of a prescription drug,’ " Sorrell v. IMS Health Inc. , 564 U.S. 552, 559, 131 S.Ct. 2653, 180 L.Ed.2d 544 (2011) ; "editorializing," FCC v. League of Women Voters of Cal. , 468 U.S. 364, 382–383, and n. 14, 104 S.Ct. 3106, 82 L.Ed.2d 278 (1984) ; " ‘[publication] for philatelic, numismatic, educational, historical, or newsworthy purposes,’ " Regan v. Time, Inc. , 468 U.S. 641, 644, 104 S.Ct. 3262, 82 L.Ed.2d 487 (1984) ; and "anonymous speech," McIntyre v. Ohio Elections Comm'n , 514 U.S. 334, 348, 357, 115 S.Ct. 1511, 131 L.Ed.2d 426 (1995). These speech categories are no more "specific" or "substantive" than messages regarding off-premises activities. And some of these examples, like "editorializing" or publishing "newsworthy" information, are clearly less so. What unites these speech restrictions is that their application turns "on the nature of the message being conveyed," Carey v. Brown , 447 U.S. 455, 461, 100 S.Ct. 2286, 65 L.Ed.2d 263 (1980), not whether they regulate specific or general categories of speech, or whether they address substantive or non-substantive categories of speech.

We have defined content-based restrictions to include all content-based distinctions because any other rule would be incoherent. After all, off-premises advertising could be considered a "subject" or a "topic" as those words are ordinarily used. See L. D. Management Co. v. Gray , 988 F.3d 836, 839 (CA6 2021) (off-premises billboard restriction "turns on the ‘topic discussed’ " (emphasis added)). And, in any event, there is no principled way to decide whether a category of communicative content is "substantive" or "specific" enough for the majority to deem it a "topic" or "subject" worthy of heightened protection. Although off-premises advertising is a more general category of speech than some (e.g. , off-premises advertising of religious events), it is a more specific category than others (e.g. , advertising generally). The majority offers only its own ipse dixit to explain why off-premises advertising is insufficiently specific to qualify as content based under Reed . Worse still, the majority does not explain how courts should draw the line between a sufficiently substantive or specific content-based classification and one that is insufficiently substantive or specific.

On this point, Austin suggests there is no need to worry because our cases provide "guideposts" from which one can divine what "level of generality" renders a speech regulation content based. Tr. of Oral Arg. 18, 24. To be sure, that is the sort of inquiry the majority's opaque test invites. But Reed directed us elsewhere—to the text of the law in question and whether that law " ‘on its face’ draws distinctions based on the message a speaker conveys." 576 U.S. at 163, 135 S.Ct. 2218. The majority's holding that some rules based on content are not, as it turns out, content based nullifies Reed ’s clear test.

B

The majority offers several reasons why its approach is consistent with Reed and other cases. None of these arguments is persuasive. Instead, they only serve to underscore the Court's ill-advised departure from our doctrine.

1

The majority first suggests that deeming Austin's sign code content based would require us to adopt an "extreme" reinterpretation of Reed . Ante , at 1471. Specifically, the majority faults the Court of Appeals for concluding that Austin's regulation was content based because, to enforce the off-premises rule, " ‘[a] reader must ask: who is the speaker and what is the speaker saying’ "? Ibid. (quoting 972 F.3d 696, 706 (CA5 2020) ). In the majority's view, Reed cannot stand for such a simplistic read-the-sign test.

The majority's skepticism is misplaced. We have often acknowledged that the need to examine the content of a message is a strong indicator that a speech regulation is content based. One year before Reed , for example, we stated that an abortion clinic buffer-zone law "would be content based if it required enforcement authorities to examine the content of the message that is conveyed to determine whether a violation has occurred." McCullen v. Coakley , 573 U.S. 464, 479, 134 S.Ct. 2518, 189 L.Ed.2d 502 (2014) (internal quotation marks omitted). That statement was not an outlier. See, e.g. , Arkansas Writers’ Project, Inc. v. Ragland , 481 U.S. 221, 230, 107 S.Ct. 1722, 95 L.Ed.2d 209 (1987) (tax exemption for periodicals "uniformly devoted to religion or sports" was content based because it required state officials to "examine the content of the message" (internal quotation marks omitted)); Forsyth County v. Nationalist Movement , 505 U.S. 123, 134, 112 S.Ct. 2395, 120 L.Ed.2d 101 (1992) (regulation requiring parade organizers to pay a fee depending on the security costs anticipated for the event was content based because "[i]n order to assess accurately the cost of security for parade participants, the administrator must necessarily examine the content of the message that is conveyed" (internal quotation marks omitted)); League of Women Voters , 468 U.S. at 366, 383, 104 S.Ct. 3106 (law forbidding public broadcasting stations from "engag[ing] in editorializing" was content based because it required "enforcement authorities [to] necessarily examine the content of the message that is conveyed" (internal quotation marks omitted)).

Ultimately, the majority's objection to the Court of Appeals’ reliance on a read-the-sign test is a red herring; its real objection is to Reed ’s rule that any law that draws distinctions based on communicative content is content based.

2

The majority next argues that Austin's sign code is content neutral under our precedents. See ante , at 1472 – 1474. But none of the cases the majority cites supports its crabbed view of what constitutes a content-based restriction.

First, in Heffron v. International Soc. for Krishna Consciousness, Inc. , 452 U.S. 640, 101 S.Ct. 2559, 69 L.Ed.2d 298 (1981), the Court upheld, as content neutral, an ordinance providing that the "[s]ale or distribution of any merchandise, including printed or written material," could occur only from certain booths at the fairgrounds. Id. , at 643, 101 S.Ct. 2559 (internal quotation marks omitted). Such a statute is facially content neutral under Reed because it does not " ‘on its face’ dra[w] distinctions based on the message a speaker conveys" when selling or distributing merchandise subject to the ordinance. 576 U.S. at 163, 135 S.Ct. 2218. True, the Court construed the ordinance also to limit "fund solicitation operations," 452 U.S. at 644, 101 S.Ct. 2559, but that was not, as the majority claims, a prohibition on "asking for donations," ante , at 1473. Rather, anyone was free to "as[k] for donations" wherever he liked, because the ordinance did "not prevent respondents from wandering throughout the fairgrounds and directing interested donors or purchasers to their booth." 452 U.S. at 664, n. 2, 101 S.Ct. 2559 (BLACKMUN, J., concurring in part and dissenting in part). Then, once "at the booth," the donor could "make a contribution." Ibid.

Second, in Cantwell v. Connecticut , 310 U.S. 296, 60 S.Ct. 900, 84 L.Ed. 1213 (1940), the Court invalidated a licensing system for religious and charitable solicitation while acknowledging in dicta that a State could regulate the time, place, and manner of solicitation. Id. , at 304, 307, 60 S.Ct. 900. But here, we are not faced with a true time, place, or manner restriction, as even the majority concedes. See ante , at 1472. And, in any event, Cantwell did not suggest that a content-based restriction could be sustained as a time, place, or manner restriction; its analysis focused predominantly on the plaintiff ’s free exercise claim; and the case predated our modern content-neutrality doctrine by nearly three decades. Thus, nothing in Heffron or Cantwell supports the majority's narrow approach to identifying content-based restrictions.

The majority says only that Austin's sign code is "similar" to a time-place-manner restriction, citing Frisby v. Schultz , 487 U.S. 474, 108 S.Ct. 2495, 101 L.Ed.2d 420 (1988). Ante, at 1472. But Frisby upheld an ordinance that regulated only where picketing may take place and not what message the picketers could communicate. See 487 U.S. at 477, 108 S.Ct. 2495 (ordinance made it "unlawful for any person to engage in picketing before or about the residence or dwelling of any individual" (internal quotation marks omitted)); cf. Hill v. Colorado , 530 U.S. 703, 766, 120 S.Ct. 2480, 147 L.Ed.2d 597 (2000) (KENNEDY, J., dissenting) ("[n]o examination of the content of a speaker's message is required to determine whether an individual is picketing").

Finally, the majority argues that we have "previously understood distinctions between on-premises and off-premises signs ... to be content neutral." Ante , at 1473. To be sure, in both Suffolk Outdoor Adv. Co. v. Hulse , 439 U.S. 808, 99 S.Ct. 66, 58 L.Ed.2d 101 (1978), and Metromedia , Inc. v. San Diego , 453 U.S. 490, 503–512, 101 S.Ct. 2882, 69 L.Ed.2d 800 (1981) (plurality opinion), this Court suggested that some restrictions on off-premises advertising were constitutional. And later, in Members of City Council of Los Angeles v. Taxpayers for Vincent , 466 U.S. 789, 104 S.Ct. 2118, 80 L.Ed.2d 772 (1984), the Court described Metromedia as upholding "a content-neutral prohibition against the use of billboards." 466 U.S. at 807, 104 S.Ct. 2118 (emphasis added). But the statement in Vincent was dictum, and, as the majority concedes, both our summary decision in Suffolk and the plurality opinion in Metromedia sanctioned off-premises restrictions only insofar as they applied to commercial speech. Ante , at 1474. That is, the "Court did not need to decide"—and did not decide—"whether the off-premises prohibition was content based" because restrictions on commercial speech are "subject to intermediate scrutiny in any event." Ibid.

3

The majority also claims that finding Austin's sign code to be content based "would render the majority opinion in Reed irreconcilable with" Justice ALITO's Reed concurrence. Ante , at 1475, n. 6. In particular, Justice ALITO identified nine different types of sign regulations that he believed "would not be content based," including "[r]ules distinguishing between on-premises and off-premises signs" and "[r]ules imposing time restrictions on signs advertising a one-time event." 576 U.S. at 174–175, 135 S.Ct. 2218. The majority evidently believes that these two types of sign regulations necessarily turn on a sign's communicative content, like the off-premises sign restriction at issue here.

That reading of the Reed concurrence makes little sense. First, there is no reason to interpret the concurrence as referring to off-premises or one-time-event rules that turn on a sign's communicative content. Doing so would make those two rules categorically different from the other seven, none of which would ever turn on message content. See, e.g. , id. , at 174, 135 S.Ct. 2218 ("Rules distinguishing between lighted and unlighted signs"). And although off-premises and one-time-event rules could be drafted in terms of a sign's communicative content, as is true here, they need not be. "There might be many formulations of an on/off-premises distinction that are content-neutral." Thomas v. Bright , 937 F.3d 721, 733 (CA6 2019) ; see also ante , at 1480, n. 1 (ALITO, J., concurring in judgment in part and dissenting in part) (explaining that "[i]n ordinary usage" an "off-premises" sign is one that is not "attached to or located in close proximity to a building"). For instance, a city could define " ‘an o[n]-premise[s] sign as any sign within 500 feet of a building,’ " 937 F.3d at 732, or a sign that is installed by " ‘a business ... licensed to occupy ... the premises where the sign is located,’ " Brief for Summus Outdoor as Amicus Curiae 10. As for regulations of one-time-event signs, Austin itself amended its sign code, at the behest of its lawyers, specifically to make its ordinance content neutral. See Austin, Tex., City Code § 25–10–102(D) (2021); App. 152. Thus, interpreting Justice ALITO's concurrence as referring to rules that turn on communicative content, as opposed to rules that are content neutral, is unwarranted.

Second, it would be strange to interpret the concurrence as proclaiming that all off-premises sign restrictions are content neutral considering the longstanding dispute over that question. In fact, 20 years before Reed , then-Judge Alito opined that there was "no easy answer to [the] question" whether "exceptions for ‘for sale’ signs and signs relating to on-site activities" would render a sign code content based. Rappa v. New Castle County , 18 F.3d 1043, 1080 (CA3 1994) (concurring opinion); see also, e.g. , Ackerley Communications of Mass., Inc. v. Cambridge , 88 F.3d 33, 36, n. 7 (CA1 1996) ("In ‘commonsense’ terms, the distinction surely is content-based because determining whether a sign must stay up or must come down requires consideration of the message it carries"); Norton Outdoor Adv., Inc. v. Arlington Heights , 69 OhioSt.2d 539, 541, 433 N.E.2d 198, 200 (1982) ("In prohibiting all forms of offsite billboard advertising, the ordinance is thus inescapably directed to the content of protected speech"). Ultimately, it seems quite unlikely that Justice ALITO's quick recital of some content-neutral rules purported to pre-emptively decide an issue that had long perplexed federal and state courts. 4

Near the end of its analysis, the majority invokes an allegedly "unbroken tradition of on-/off-premises distinctions" that it claims "counsels against" faithful application of Reed . Ante , at 1475. To be sure, history and tradition are relevant to identifying and defining those "few limited areas" where, "[f]rom 1791 to the present," "the First Amendment has permitted restrictions upon the content of speech." Brown v. Entertainment Merchants Assn. , 564 U.S. 786, 791, 131 S.Ct. 2729, 180 L.Ed.2d 708 (2011) (internal quotation marks omitted); see supra , at 1482, n. 1. But the majority openly admits that off-premises regulations "were not present [at] the founding." Ante , at 1474. And while it asserts that "large outdoor advertisements proliferated in the 1800s," ibid. , it offers no evidence of any content-based restrictions from that period, let alone off-premises restrictions on noncommercial speech. The earliest example of an off-premises restriction that the majority cites arose in Packer Corp. v. Utah , 285 U.S. 105, 52 S.Ct. 273, 76 L.Ed. 643 (1932), but that case involved a restriction on commercial advertising and did not even feature a First Amendment claim. See id. , at 108–112, 52 S.Ct. 273.

Ultimately, the majority's only "historical" support is that regulations like Austin's "proliferated following the enactment of the Highway Beautification Act of 1965." Ante , at 1469. The majority's suggestion that the First Amendment should yield to a speech restriction that "proliferated"— under pressure from the Federal Government—some two centuries after the founding is both "startling and dangerous." United States v. Stevens , 559 U.S. 460, 470, 130 S.Ct. 1577, 176 L.Ed.2d 435 (2010). This Court has never hinted that the government can, with a few decades of regulation, subject "new categories of speech" to less exacting First Amendment scrutiny. Id. , at 472, 130 S.Ct. 1577.

Regardless, even if this allegedly "unbroken tradition" did not fall short by a century or two, the majority offers no explanation why historical regulation is relevant to the question whether the off-premises restriction is content based under Reed and our modern content-neutrality jurisprudence. If Austin had met its burden of identifying a historical tradition of analogous regulation—as can be done, say, for obscenity or defamation—that would not make the off-premises rule content neutral. It might simply mean that the off-premises rule is a constitutional form of content-based discrimination. But content neutrality under Reed is an empirical question, not a historical one. Thus, the majority's historical argument is not only meritless but misguided.

C

Despite asserting that the Court of Appeals’ analysis under Reed would "contravene numerous precedents," ante , at 1474, the majority identifies no decision of this Court supporting the idea that a speech restriction is not content based so long as it regulates a sufficiently broad or non-substantive category of communicative content. In fact, there is only one case that could possibly validate the majority's aberrant analysis: Hill v. Colorado . That Hill is the majority's only support underscores the danger that today's decision poses to the First Amendment.

Hill involved a law that prohibited persons outside abortion clinics from knowingly approaching within eight feet of another person without consent "for the purpose of ... engaging in oral protest, education, or counseling." 530 U.S. at 707, 120 S.Ct. 2480 (internal quotation marks omitted). Hill concluded, implausibly, that this regulation was content neutral. The majority's reasoning in this case is just as implausible. The majority asserts that the off-premises rule is not content based because it does not target a sufficiently "specific" or "substantive" category of communications. Ante , at 1472. Hill correspondingly held that restrictions on "protest, education, or counseling" were not content-based classifications because they cover "an extremely broad category of communications." 530 U.S. at 723, 120 S.Ct. 2480. The majority also tries to disguise its redefinition of content neutrality by characterizing Austin's rule as a "neutral, location-based" restriction. Ante , at 1471. So too did Hill try to conceal its doctrinal innovation by characterizing the buffer-zone law as a neutral "place restriction." 530 U.S. at 723, 120 S.Ct. 2480. Finally, the majority finds it immaterial that Austin's rule can be enforced only by "reading a [sign] to determine whether it" contains an off-premises message. Ante , at 1472. Hill likewise found it irrelevant that "the content of the oral statements" would need to "be examined to determine whether" the prohibition applied. 530 U.S. at 720, 120 S.Ct. 2480.

The parallel between the majority's opinion and Hill should be discomforting given that Hill represented "an unprecedented departure" from this Court's First Amendment jurisprudence. Id. , at 772, 120 S.Ct. 2480 (KENNEDY, J., dissenting). Its content-neutrality analysis was, as Justice SCALIA explained, "absurd" given that the buffer-zone law was "obviously and undeniably content based." Id. , at 742–743, 120 S.Ct. 2480 (dissenting opinion). First Amendment scholars from across the ideological spectrum agree. See, e.g. , M. McConnell, Professor Michael W. McConnell's Response, in K. Sullivan, Sex, Money, and Groups: Free Speech and Association Decisions in the October 1999 Term, 28 Pepperdine L. Rev. 723, 748 (2001) ("The Court said that this statute is content-neutral. I just literally cannot see how they could possibly come to that conclusion"); Colloquium, id ., at 750, 120 S.Ct. 2480 (Laurence Tribe stating Hill "was slam-dunk simple and slam-dunk wrong"); R. Fallon, Strict Judicial Scrutiny, 54 UCLA L. Rev. 1267, 1298, and n. 174 (2007) ( Hill "unconvincingly ... maintain[ed] that a content-based restriction on speech [was] not really content-based"). And, since Hill , this Court has all but interred its flawed content-neutrality analysis in both McCullen , see supra , at 1486 – 1487, and Reed . See Price v. Chicago , 915 F.3d 1107, 1118 (CA7 2019) ("In the wake of McCullen and Reed , it's not too strong to say that what Hill explicitly rejected is now prevailing law").

The majority's refusal to acknowledge Hill simply underscores the decision's defunct status. Again, Hill is the only case that could support the majority's ill-conceived content-neutrality analysis, and yet the majority disclaims reliance on it. Lower courts should take the majority's disclaimer at face value: Hill is "a decision that we do not cite." Ante , at 1475. And today's decision amounts to little more than an ad hoc exemption for the "location-based" and supposedly "content-agnostic on-/off-premises distinction." Ibid .

Even so, the majority's approach should offer little comfort because arbitrary carveouts from Reed undermine the "clear and firm rule governing content neutrality" that we understood to be "an essential means of protecting the freedom of speech." 576 U.S. at 171, 135 S.Ct. 2218. The majority's deviation from that "clear and firm rule" poses two serious threats to the First Amendment's protections.

First, transforming Reed ’s clear definition of "content based regulation" back into an opaque and malleable "term of art" turns the concept of content neutrality into a "vehicl[e] for the implementation of individual judges’ policy preferences." Tennessee v. Lane , 541 U.S. 509, 556, 124 S.Ct. 1978, 158 L.Ed.2d 820 (2004) (SCALIA, J., dissenting). Hill exemplifies this danger. See 530 U.S. at 742, 120 S.Ct. 2480 (SCALIA, J., dissenting) ("I have no doubt that this regulation would be deemed content based in an instant if the case before us involved antiwar protesters, or union members seeking to ‘educate’ the public about the reasons for their strike"). The majority's approach in this case is cut from the same cloth. As the majority transparently admits, it seeks to "apply [our] precedents to reach the ‘commonsense’ result " and avoid what it perceives as a "bizarre result ." Ante , at 1475 (emphasis added). But Reed mandates a "commonsense" test for content neutrality even if the result is that "laws that might seem entirely reasonable will sometimes be struck down." 576 U.S. at 163, 171, 135 S.Ct. 2218 (internal quotation marks omitted).

Second, sanctioning certain content-based classifications but not others ignores that even seemingly reasonable content-based restrictions are ready tools for those who would "suppress disfavored speech." Id ., at 167, 135 S.Ct. 2218 ; see also Hill , 530 U.S. at 743, 120 S.Ct. 2480 (SCALIA, J., dissenting) (" ‘The vice of content-based legislation ... is not that it is always used for invidious, thought-control purposes, but that it lends itself to use for those purposes’ "). This is because "the responsibility for distinguishing between" permissible and impermissible content "carries with it the potential for invidious discrimination of disfavored subjects." Cincinnati v. Discovery Network, Inc. , 507 U.S. 410, 423–424, n. 19, 113 S.Ct. 1505, 123 L.Ed.2d 99 (1993). That danger only grows when the content-based distinctions are "by no means clear," giving more leeway for government officials to punish disfavored speakers and ideas. Ibid.

The content-based distinction drawn by Austin's off-premises speech restriction is "by no means clear," ibid. , and plainly lends itself "to suppress[ing] disfavored speech," Reed , 576 U.S. at 167, 135 S.Ct. 2218. As the Court of Appeals noted, Austin's "prepared counsel" "struggled to answer whether" signs conveying messages like " ‘God Loves You,’ " " ‘Vote for Kathy,’ " or " ‘Sally makes quilts here and sells them at 3200 Main Street’ " would be regulated as off-premises signs. 972 F.3d at 706. Before us, Austin's counsel had similar difficulties, and amici have proposed dozens of religious and political messages that would be next to impossible to categorize under Austin's rule. See, e.g. , Brief for Alliance Defending Freedom et. al. as Amici Curiae 15–19; Brief for Institute for Justice as Amicus Curiae 3–9. These pervasive ambiguities offer enforcement officials ample opportunity to suppress disfavored views. And they underscore Reed ’s warning that "[i]nnocent motives do not eliminate the danger of censorship presented by a facially content-based statute." 576 U.S. at 167, 135 S.Ct. 2218.

* * *

Because Reed provided a clear and neutral rule that protected the freedom of speech from governmental caprice and viewpoint discrimination, I would adhere to that precedent rather than risk resuscitating Hill . I respectfully dissent.


Summaries of

City of Austin, Tex. v. Reagan Nat'l Advert. of Austin

Supreme Court of the United States
Apr 21, 2022
142 S. Ct. 1464 (2022)

cautioning against overreading Reed's "function or purpose" language

Summary of this case from People for the Ethical Treatment of Animals, Inc. v. N.C. Farm Bureau Fed'n

In Austin, the city code in dispute defined an “off-premises sign” as “a sign advertising a business, person, activity, goods, products, or services not located on the site where the sign is installed, or that directs persons to any location not on that site.

Summary of this case from Norton Outdoor Advert. v. Vill. of St. Bernard

explaining that regulation of speech is content-based if it " 'applies to particular speech because of the topic discussed or the idea or message expressed' "

Summary of this case from Md. Shall Issue, Inc. v. Anne Arundel Cnty.

noting that "restrictions on speech may require some evaluation of the speech and nonetheless remain content neutral"

Summary of this case from United States v. Mackey

In City of Austin v. Reagan Nat'l Advertising of Austin, LLC, — U.S. —, 142 S. Ct. 1464, 212 L.Ed.2d 418 (2022), the Supreme Court upheld a municipal signage law that differentiated between signs that advertised on- versus off-premises services and activities.

Summary of this case from Sec. & Exch. Comm'n v. AT&T Inc.

noting that billboards have been regulated for years and holding that an off-site sign prohibition is not “content-based” regulation of speech and therefore not entitled to strict scrutiny

Summary of this case from The Advantage of Advert. v. City of Opelika
Case details for

City of Austin, Tex. v. Reagan Nat'l Advert. of Austin

Case Details

Full title:CITY OF AUSTIN, TEXAS, PETITIONER v. REAGAN NATIONAL ADVERTISING OF…

Court:Supreme Court of the United States

Date published: Apr 21, 2022

Citations

142 S. Ct. 1464 (2022)

Citing Cases

Reagan Nat'l Advert. of Austin v. City of Austin

The amendments, though, do not affect this appeal. City of Austin v. Reagan Nat'l Advert. of Austin, LLC, 142…

Reagan Nat'l Advert. of Austin, Inc. v. City of Austin

The amendments, though, do not affect this appeal. City of Austin v. Reagan Nat'l Advert. of Austin, LLC, —…